25 June 2020

Bringing a Hammer to the Chess Board

Why Doctrinal-Conceptual Legal Thinking is Futile in Dealing with Autocratizing Regimes

Imagine a perverted chess competition during which one of the competitors takes an iron hammer to every single chess match where, in front of everyone, he hits his opponent on the hand if the intended move seems to be too smart. If you were a member of the audience (with purely academic interest) watching this take place, then you would probably not attempt to thoroughly analyze the actual chess moves or to reconstruct the match in a chess journal either, and you would frown upon those who do for their hypocrisy. Doing so presupposes that the result of the match actually depended on the smartness of the chess moves.

The Rule of Law as a Precondition of Doctrinal-Conceptual Legal Thinking

In cases where constitutional law is slowly losing its normative force, sophisticated doctrinal-conceptual systems (Verfassungsdogmatik) may even become ridiculous and, to some degree, dishonest. While showing a very few examples of doctrinal absurdities in a judgment of a captured and subservient constitutional court can be meaningful (also in order to corroborate the claim about its captured nature), writing a thorough doctrinal analysis on such a judgment is a futile, frustrating and meaningless exercise (see the podcast by Franz C Mayer on Verfassungsblog on the Polish Constitutional Court).

A thorough doctrinal analysis can even legitimize the theater of legalism by taking seriously words which are not worth to be taken seriously. Judicial decisions of captured courts and doctrinal writings of pro-autocracy academics in these countries can be viewed as merely performative acts (as opposed to reasons). While they can be analyzed as empirical material for studying the phenomenon of rule-of-law erosion, they are unsuitable for use in thorough doctrinal, systematic-conceptual legal work. Both judicial case-law and doctrinal scholarship feed on coherence, but autocratic constitutional regimes are by their very nature ad hoc and arbitrary.1)

The picture, of course, can be differentiated: certain parts of the legal system can remain relatively intact (e.g., tort law or company law, which are politically less relevant), keeping such doctrinal-legal conceptual analyses still meaningful – while others (especially constitutional law, or just politically sensitive specific areas of constitutional law) decline. And the situation can also change from year to year: when the constitutional takeover has not yet completed, it can be entirely legitimate to try to halt it by means of thorough doctrinal-conceptual analysis (e.g. in the form of a commentary, a case-note or an amicus curiae). Once the takeover is complete, however, the same writings can acquire an unintended legitimizing function. The frontiers between the two stages are in real life not always clear or become clear retrospectively (and the question of degree can best be answered with the help of various rule-of-law indices), but in order to understand the methodological (and moral) dilemma in its extremity, it is useful to simplify here.

Throughout the legal history of 19th and 20th centuries, doctrinal-conceptual analysis received ever new boosts whenever the rule of law was extended to a new area. Judicial review of administrative acts resulted in more sophisticated doctrinal-conceptual administrative law, and the spread of constitutional courts (or supreme courts with similar competences) resulted in more sophisticated Verfassungsdogmatik. The 19th century development of the rule of law in legal reality enabled analytical jurisprudence (John Austin, Felix Somló) and doctrinal legal positivism in the area of public law (Paul Laband, Otto Mayer, Edmund Bernatzik, Ernő Nagy): concentrating on doctrinal-conceptual, instead of contextual analysis became a meaningful and plausible methodological position. With the currently ongoing constitutional erosion of the rule of law, we observe changes in the opposite direction in autocratizing countries. Methodological and theoretical approaches to law presuppose specific types of legal regimes. Being purely positivist-doctrinalist is one of the meaningful methodological positions in countries where the rule of law is in excellent shape; but staying exclusively positivist-doctrinalist when dealing with the constitutional law of a hybrid regime is autistic and/or cynical.

The Methodological Challenge of Autocratization for Scholarly Writing

In case of rule-of-law erosion, a key problem is the slow demise of the normative force of constitutional law, i.e. the gradually growing chasm between constitutional law and constitutional reality. In such regimes, amendments to formal legal acts have little to say about what and how things will change. If we do not want to remain blind to erosion, besides considering the formal rules, we must also examine the de facto conduct of both officials and citizens, and the narrative accompanying it (the latter includes the social mentality and the political rhetoric regarding constitutional institutions). If in our academic work we are interested in describing and explaining erosion, we should adjust methodologically to the partially non-legal nature of erosion.

Especially during the advanced stage of autocratization (when the erosion has already been established many times, both in scholarship and in various reports of international organizations), it is better to adjust our methods. Traditional doctrinal-legal analysis will not tell you anything new anyway (except that autocratic regimes can be skillful and creative with nasty legal tricks), and you will look like a fool for taking the pretended legalism of the regime seriously, yet again another time.

Therefore, the currently ongoing autocratization does not simply deliver a new set of questions for constitutional lawyers, but it also motivates us to rethink the methods of constitutional scholarship. Purely doctrinal-conceptual analyses are likely to become less (in certain countries perhaps much less) attractive than before. And institutionalist analyses combining legal doctrinal-conceptual and social science methods are likely to gain further popularity in the future.

PS. The dilemmas are somewhat different, if the issue is not simply to understand and explain autocratization for the scholarly community (wherever you are, maybe even at a foreign university in a stabile constitutional democracy), but if you have to teach constitutional law at a university which is geographically located in an actual autocratizing country. In the latter case, difficult moral and practical choices have to be made every day, but that should be the topic of another blog entry.

References

References
1 A terminological remark for conceptual clarity: by autocracy or autocratic I mean in the present contribution the lack of the rule of law. For the relationship between democracy and the rule of law during erosion, see in more detail András Jakab, What Can Constitutional Law Do Against the Erosion of Democracy and the Rule of Law? On the Interconnectedness of the Protection of Democracy and the Rule of Law. Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law & International Law (MPIL) Research Paper No. 2019-15. Available at SSRN (Constitutional Studies 6. 2020. 5-34).

SUGGESTED CITATION  Jakab, András: Bringing a Hammer to the Chess Board: Why Doctrinal-Conceptual Legal Thinking is Futile in Dealing with Autocratizing Regimes, VerfBlog, 2020/6/25, https://verfassungsblog.de/bringing-a-hammer-to-the-chess-board/, DOI: 10.17176/20200626-003815-0.

3 Comments

  1. Rafael A. López Murcia Thu 25 Jun 2020 at 18:37 - Reply

    Excellent contribution from Professor A. Jakab. It shows, very properly, the moral and practical dilemmas of legal thinkers in a world system disengaged from most conventional restrain and balance.

    “A system faraway from equilibrium”, as the Legal Philosopher E. Grün, from the Buenos Aires University, wrote once, in a enlighting essay.

    With best regards.

    Rafael A. López Murcia
    Tegucigalpa, Honduras, C.A.

  2. David Driesen Fri 26 Jun 2020 at 16:06 - Reply

    Excellent point. I’ve been wondering about how we define a captured court and what role doctrine plays when we are trying to see if one is captured. The new autocrats do not practice telephone justice, do they? They appoint judges whose own judicial philosophy leads them to support the regime. And the Turkish Court, at least, has sometimes ruled against the regime, even after its purges.

  3. Mark Tushnet Sun 28 Jun 2020 at 04:27 - Reply

    It seems to me that everything here turns on the distinction between “reasons” and “performative acts.” But there’s a (respectable) jurisprudence that denies the cogency of that distinction (again, within law, not necessarily in every discourse-domain). If that’s right, then “ridiculous” and “dishonest” are (merely) strong expressions of disagreement with the political positions defended by invoking the applicable doctrinal categories (at least as long as one allows, as I think one must, for the possibility that incremental changes in doctrine are admissible within the doctrinal system).

Leave A Comment Cancel reply

WRITE A COMMENT

1. We welcome your comments but you do so as our guest. Please note that we will exercise our property rights to make sure that Verfassungsblog remains a safe and attractive place for everyone. Your comment will not appear immediately but will be moderated by us. Just as with posts, we make a choice. That means not all submitted comments will be published.

2. We expect comments to be matter-of-fact, on-topic and free of sarcasm, innuendo and ad personam arguments.

3. Racist, sexist and otherwise discriminatory comments will not be published.

4. Comments under pseudonym are allowed but a valid email address is obligatory. The use of more than one pseudonym is not allowed.