12 January 2017

Constitutional Review as an Indispensable Element of the Rule of Law? Poland as the Divided State between Political and Legal Constitutionalism

1. Poland AD 2017 – The Divided State: A Snapshot Of The Current Situation

It seems, that as in Poland divide et impera becomes the maxim of the ruling party, the Polish state develops a divided identity. There is the divided Constitutional Tribunal with three illegitimate judges whose decisions might be objected by ordinary courts as invalid, and the divided Parliament which proceeds without the presence of the opposition parties or notwithstanding their protests. There is a divided academia, on the one hand supporting the current government with opinions how to solve the crisis and carry out other institutional reforms monopolizing the power, on the other strongly criticizing the ongoing measures as being in breach of the Polish Constitution. Further, there is the division among ordinary judges who may encounter a loyalty problem – either follow new decisions of the Constitutional Tribunal or try to apply the Constitution directly. There is also the Ombudsman who tries to stay neutral and intervene in all cases of potential human rights violations, including the rights of the members of the majority. Finally, there is a politically divided society, including those who are uninterested in politics, or those, who uncritically follow the government-led propaganda in the public media, and who are satisfied with the new redistribution policies rather than give the situation a critical thought.

Once a Musterkind among the new Member States of the European Union, Poland led by the Law and Justice appears deaf to the call of the European Commission to respect the rule of law. It is right on its way to diverge from the core of European values and bury the myth of its own national solidarity. At the same time, it has become a divided state between political and legal constitutionalism, which shows particularly in the constitutional crisis over the Constitutional Tribunal.

2. Legal Versus Political Constitutionalism

According to the main tenet of liberal constitutionalism the rule of law, democracy, and human rights are indispensable elements of a modern state. Nevertheless, modern constitutionalism does not offer specific solutions as how to organize these principles in practice, as each of them imposes limitations on others – the rule of law and human rights restrain the majority rule, while democracy and human rights provide for substantive standards of the rule of law. Notwithstanding the global trend to envision the constitutional review in constitutions, the concept of constitutionalism does not per se mandate the establishment of constitutional courts. Instead, constitutionalism requires effective guarantees of access to a court and judicial independence as the primary conditions of the legal protection of individual rights. Is the establishment of constitutional courts just a political matter, given the fact that the scope of competences assigned to constitutional courts vary from country to country?

The events concerning the Constitutional Tribunal in Poland show that a political attack on the constitutional court marks the endemic conflict between political and legal constitutionalism. This is particularly exposed in the Expert Report commissioned by the Speaker of the Lower Chamber of Parliament in July 2016. In the report a group of constitutional experts proposed a novel interpretation of the Polish Constitution which emphasizes the supremacy of democracy over the abstract principle of rule of law and delivers a concept of separation of powers based on the supremacy of Parliament. It promotes the need to weaken the position of the Polish Constitutional Tribunal in order to prevent the expansion of “juristocracy” and “judicialization of politics.” While this interpretation coincides with the government’s plan to “reform” the constitutional review in Poland (proposed already during the first rule of the Law and Justice Party in 2005-2007), its implications reveal the fragility of fundamental assumptions of modern constitutionalism.

Despite its meanwhile very detailed chronology, the Polish conflict concerning the Constitutional Tribunal poses a general question about the scope of legislative interventions in the status and the organization of the constitutional court. After a set of amendments to the law on the Constitutional Tribunal addressing the composition of the Tribunal, the attendance quorum and the sequence of hearing cases, the most recent change regards the status of the judges and the appointment of the acting Chief Justice by the President of the Republic in case the office of the Chief Justice remains vacant.

From the viewpoint of the Venice Commission and the European Commission these changes had substantially limited the effective operation of the Tribunal. Even though the Constitutional Tribunal subsequently declared most of them to be unconstitutional, the government refused to publish these decisions in the Official Journal contrary to Art. 190 (2) of the Polish Constitution. The reason not to publish the judgments was based on allegations that the Tribunal, by not applying the Act on the Constitutional Tribunal subject to its review, violated the Constitution.

The lack of a compromise regarding the refusal to swear in the judges by the President of the Republic, and to publish the judgments of the Constitutional Tribunal, led the European Commission to initiate for the first time the new EU Framework procedure to strengthen the Rule of Law against Poland. Having found that there is a serious risk to the rule of law in Poland the Commission issued a recommendation to the Polish government. However, what is legally problematic in this recommendation is the criterion of „effectiveness“ of the constitutional justice as there are, in fact, no common normative standards of the effectiveness of constitutional review within the EU.

The legal assessment of such effectiveness might therefore vary, in particular if comparing the availability and admissibility of constitutional  complaint mechanisms, and be subject to many argumentative scenarios. For example the European Court of Human Rights considers the constitutional complaint in Poland as an effective remedy in individual cases only in specific circumstances (cp. Szott-Medyńska v. Poland, App. No. 47414/99, decision of 9 October 2003). Therefore, the EU Commission’s concerns as to the rule of law in Poland needs to be more related to the currently binding Polish Constitution.  In other words, a serious threat to the rule of law in Poland results in the first place from the fact that the President and the government violated the Constitution by inter alia ignoring a valid decision of the Constitutional Tribunal.

Yet, the crisis over the Constitutional Tribunal could also be viewed as a consequence of a number of structural and institutional problems that made the “court packing” a politically viable strategy. Over the years they have led to a staggering detachment of the Constitutional Tribunal from the people who viewed the Constitutional Tribunal as yet another state institution predominantly involved in ensuring a hierarchical control of legal norms, rather than a human rights court with a direct impact on their lives. In fact though, given the limitations of the Polish model of constitutional complaint regarding its scope and the form of redress it provides, the effectiveness of constitutional review with regard to individual cases in Poland could be generally doubted. This could be one of many reasons that made it easier for the political majority to attack the constitutional court.

3. Constitutional Review and the Rule of Law in Germany

Such a political court packing strategy appears to be unthinkable for example in Germany with the possibly strongest constitutional court worldwide, whose position is owed not only to historical reasons related with the adoption of the Basic Law in 1949, but to other factors such as a very confident exercise of constitutional review and the constant popularity of the individual constitutional complaint. Despite the fact that until 2015 only 2,3% of individual complaints have been actually successful, they led to landmark decisions with a perceivable socio-political impact. It is remarkable though that the competence of review individual constitutional complaints has developed as a product of historical experiences and political decisions rather than the doctrinal evolution of the concept of the rule of law.

While in Poland the legislative changes regarding the organization and procedure before the Constitutional Tribunal have been introduced without a constitutional amendment, one could ask whether similar amendments would be permissible, under the Basic Law. The German Federal Constitutional Court’s position as a constitutional organ, with a wide range of autonomy that comes with it, on top of judicial independency, is legally and politically recognised. The Court’s role as a “political actor”, has, however, been also subject to academic and political debates, some even suggesting to alter the Court’s competences with regard to the individual constitutional complaints, owed, however, in part to the high application numbers and the low success quotas, being considered to be blocking the Court’s capacities (cp. Entlastung des Bundesverfassungsgerichts. Bericht der Kommission der Bundesministeriums der Justiz (Report), Bonn, 1997).

In the first place, the German constitution allows the legislature to design the constitutional court’s organisation and procedure in a legislative act (cp. Art. 94 (2) of the Basic Law). In fact, the Federal Constitutional Court Act (Bundesverfassungsgerichtsgesetz) of 12 March 1951 has been subject to legislative modification throughout the years. It is not obvious, however, in how far the legislature’s constitutional margin of organisation is capped by the principle of the rule of law. Clearly, changes of the Court’s competences laid down in the constitution (Art. 93 of the Basic Law) would require a constitutional amendment. According to the “eternity clause” of the Art. 79(3) of the Basic Law, the inviolable guarantee of human dignity and the binding of public authority to the basic rights (Art. 1 Basic Law), as well as the principles enumerated in Article 20 of the Basic Law – such as the republican form of the government, democracy or welfare state – are unamendable. Yet, neither the rule of law nor the right to constitutional justice are explicitly referred to in Art. 79 (3) of the Basic Law. Furthermore, since the principle of the rule of law itself is not explicitly mentioned in Art. 20 of the Basic Law, the Federal Constitutional Court had once detected that the Rechtsstaatsprinzip itself is actually not included in the eternity clause of Art. 79 (3) (Judgement of 15 December 1970, BVerfGE 30, 1 (24, 28). Even if, generally,  the right to effective legal remedies has been considered an essential part of the principle of the rule of law, it remains open, as to whether it includes the revision by a constitutional court. Rather crucial in this context is the guarantee of an independent control by a court. Although, one could moreover read the constitutional commitment of all organs of public authority to fundamental rights (Art. 1 (3) of the Basic Law) in favour of an independent control mechanism, yet again, it is not expressly stated that the guarantee of the commitment to fundamental rights requires a constitutional court as a safeguard against fundamental rights’ infringements. Therefore, the suggestion that the constitutional review is per se a necessary element of the rule of law and even unamendable is legally less solid than it occurs at the first glance

4. Conclusion

It appears that a monopoly over the constitutional review by constitutional courts is not a mandatory component of the legal concept of a democratic state governed by the rule of law. Even in the context of the Basic Law, a constitutional framework that has created a very strong constitutional jurisdiction, a clear argumentation in favour of constitutional review as a tangible element of the rule of law, and therefore an indispensable element of constitutionality, is rather blurred. In fact, the power of constitutional courts appears to be a political matter which depends on the political majority and public support notwithstanding their desirability in certain political contexts, in particular in countries with relatively young democratic traditions and authoritarian pasts. This might not be the best news for modern constitutionalism but one we need to be aware of, in particular in times of the recent re-rise of populist movements, illiberal disenchantment, and anti-establishment rhetoric – not only in Poland.

 


SUGGESTED CITATION  Mrozek, Anna; Śledzińska-Simon, Anna: Constitutional Review as an Indispensable Element of the Rule of Law? Poland as the Divided State between Political and Legal Constitutionalism, VerfBlog, 2017/1/12, https://verfassungsblog.de/constitutional-review-as-an-indispensable-element-of-the-rule-of-law-poland-as-the-divided-state-between-political-and-legal-constitutionalism/, DOI: 10.17176/20170112-091650.

4 Comments

  1. David Stephenson Thu 12 Jan 2017 at 09:47 - Reply

    Start at the beginning please! In 1989 the Communists, who were also running the leadership of Solidarity (established fact, beyond all discussion), agreed with Solidarity that the first government would legalize all the theft that occurred during Communism and that there would be no post-Communism “persecution” of Communist criminals. Moreover, it was agreed that the media and judiciary would remain staunchly “culturally Communist” in outlook – to be ensured by having all important positions in the hands of people trusted by – and often closely related to – high-ranking Communists. Capital investment through the banks and stock exchange went to businessmen who all happened to be well-placed Communists. The economy was aimed at: (i) ensuring low wages through having almost no social welfare, and (ii) no tax for foreign Big Business – all tax was to be ‘eaten’ through tax evasion schemes just being set up by Jean-Claude Juncker in Luxemburg. The apogee of absurdity was reached in 1995, when Poland had a choice between the open former Communist Kwasniewski and the then hidden Communist agent Lech Wałęsa. Changes of party name masked the works of the Establishment – until the Internet came along. People discovered who, for example, the Polish ambassador to the US was https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ryszard_Schnepf The media, which was monolithic in outlook (both public and private media), was seen to be utterly corrupt and staffed with sons and daughters of Party apparatchiks. Two leading judges in the Constitutional Tribunal – Kieres and Rzepliński – were shown to be politicians in hiding. Both had stymied investigations into Communist-era political slayings. Funny that – Kieres had been head of Poland’s “Truth Commission”! Rzepliński had also been an employee of George Soros, a well-known political extremist who has stated that he wishes to see mass – and specifically Muslim – immigration into Europe, though he hasn’t stated why. In terms of wealth-creation, Poland has done relatively well, compared to 1989. But what a low base to compare with! But extreme poverty persisted – only in the last few months have any politicians done anything about it. Introducing CHILD BENEFIT is a game-changer. Western companies, as planned, have fared decidedly better. Germany, in contrast, had its industrial base “re-booted” in 1945. German (not foreign) companies were encouraged, there was no desire to play radical politics with the media or judiciary. Old Nazis were generally left in peace, but had not amassed fortunes like the Commies did in Poland – they had little to defend. In Poland, the “law-abiding” Ultra Crony Capitalist Establishment stacked the Constitutional Tribunal with 14 of its 15 members. The “international community” said nothing. Democracy was unimportant then. You can clearly see the machinations of naked power at play here. Donald Tusk shut down the heavyweight newspaper Rzeczpospolita because it reported that part of the Smolensk wreck had tested positive for explosive residue. Can you imagine the uproar if Merkel shut down Die Welt over reporting the Cologne sex attacks? The “international community” was silent. Might is right.

  2. ajo Thu 12 Jan 2017 at 10:06 - Reply

    I love You David Stevenson :D.
    Right place at the point. Hypocrisy is still in vogue.

  3. Christian Boulanger Thu 12 Jan 2017 at 15:14 - Reply

    @Stephenson: Good heavens, what a long comment without any relationship to what is written in the article. But very typical. We are still waiting for some interesting legal arguments supporting the actions of the PiS government against the constitutional court. Conspiracy theories, EU bashing, whataboutisms etc. just won’t do it.

  4. Law as Integrity Thu 12 Jan 2017 at 18:20 - Reply

    Thanks for this interesting contribution. Just one short comment: Although you may be right that a constitutional court is empirically not a mandatory component of the rule of law, independent control of politics as a principle for sure is. So who else could do the job?

Leave A Comment

WRITE A COMMENT

1. We welcome your comments but you do so as our guest. Please note that we will exercise our property rights to make sure that Verfassungsblog remains a safe and attractive place for everyone. Your comment will not appear immediately but will be moderated by us. Just as with posts, we make a choice. That means not all submitted comments will be published.

2. We expect comments to be matter-of-fact, on-topic and free of sarcasm, innuendo and ad personam arguments.

3. Racist, sexist and otherwise discriminatory comments will not be published.

4. Comments under pseudonym are allowed but a valid email address is obligatory. The use of more than one pseudonym is not allowed.




Explore posts related to this:
Constitutional Review, Polish Constitutional Court


Other posts about this region:
Polen