14 July 2016

After Brexit: Time for a further Decoupling of European and National Citizenship?

The aftermath of the Brexit referendum has produced a whole series of uncertainties, many of which surround citizenship. Much of the UK debate in the last weeks has focused on the varying levels of guarantees UK politicians are willing make to EU citizens who have made their lives in the UK. German politicians, up to and including Germany’s Vice-Chancellor, have proposed (following ideas advanced in the Verfassungsblog) to secure an easier path to citizenship for Britons living in other EU states. Finally, what will happen to the citizens of those parts of the UK who voted decisively to remain in the Union? Over 5 million Scots, and 1.8 million Northern Irish, face the removal of EU citizenship rights they voted in large numbers to keep.

At the root of this conundrum are classical concepts of EU citizenship law. The key is the idea that EU and national citizenship are decisively coupled. It is for the Member States to decide who ‘belongs’ to their national polity and who, by extension, can benefit from European citizenship and the rights attached to that status. EU citizenship is, as the CJEU famously laid down in Grzelczyk, ‘destined to be the fundamental status of nationals of the Member States’. Yet it is also meant to be a status fundamental to all EU citizens ‘enabling those who find themselves in the same situation to enjoy the same treatment in law irrespective of their nationality’.

Some of the reactions to Brexit from both the Union and the Member States call into question whether there truly is something fundamentally European about European citizenship. In the Scottish example, it is the UK government that, at a stroke, can deprive its nationals of European citizenship rights they have enjoyed for more than two decades. For the President of the European Council, Donald Tusk, the issue of Scotland’s EU membership is ‘a matter for the UK’. It is for UK politics to determine whether the state (as a whole) leaves the EU and whether, therefore, its citizens (or a group of them) may enjoy rights independently of those their government is willing to grant them under domestic law.

One can wonder how fundamental European citizenship really is if the President of one of the Union’s highest executive bodies can consider its withdrawal from millions of UK nationals an ‘internal matter’ for which the Union itself is neither (legally) competent nor (politically) accountable. At precisely the most crucial moment – when the status under EU law not just of isolated unfortunate individuals, but of a whole population, is threatened – EU citizenship seems to have lost its normative purchase.

Some years ago, and with no Brexit in view, then Advocate General Poiares Maduro espoused a different vision of European citizenship. While ‘assuming nationality of a Member State’, it is ‘also a legal and political concept independent of that of nationality’. European citizenship ‘unites the peoples of Europe’, based on ‘their mutual commitment to open their respective bodies politic to other European citizens and to construct a new form of civic and political allegiance on a European scale’. The concrete legal ramifications of Maduro’s political vision in Rottmann were that a Member State’s decision to withdraw naturalization came under the scrutiny of EU law because that decision could also entail a removal of the status of European citizenship. In Ruiz Zambrano, the Court supplemented the protection of this status with the requirement that European citizens must be able to genuinely enjoy the substance of their European citizenship rights. Hence, while the European Union has no original or autonomous competence to confer European citizenship, it can and will protect it once acquired against interference by the Member States

Of course, life after Brexit is different, and not simply in view of the sheer number of citizens the EU is bound to loose. The UK’s decision to leave the Union arguably eliminates the basis upon which UK nationals could acquire the status of European citizenship. At the same time, European citizens from the UK insist that their country cannot strip them of the rights they have acquired under that very status. How should the Union move forward?

The most obvious move is to think radically. A further de-coupling of EU citizenship from national membership would allow the Union to replicate the emancipatory move of Van Gend en Loos – to liberate individuals from the preferences of their states. De-coupling would signify a constitutional recognition that rights acquired as European citizens really are ‘fundamental’: integral to individual personhood and therefore inscribed into the deep structure of an autonomous EU legal order such that they cannot simply be done away with by inter-governmental agreement. De-coupling would allow those UK nationals –be they from London, Scotland or any other part – to retain their European citizenship rights of free movement and non-discrimination in other EU states if they so wished, by virtue of their continued membership in the European polity. While the decision to grant Union citizenship may still rest with the Member States, via Member State nationality, the decision to withdraw it would rest with the individual EU citizen (who may also wish to renounce that citizenship if they so choose).

This vision may make better sense of Maduro’s conception of a European polity based on the mutual commitment of its peoples to construct a new form of civic and political allegiance on a European scale. The introduction of European citizenship has served to counteract the unfortunate tendency on the part of the Union to treat nationals of the Member States as free-moving market commodities. It has yet to defeat the temptation of Member States – in the Brexit campaign as elsewhere – to portray free-moving European citizens as free riders on their national welfare systems. Both perspectives, however, miss out on the most fundamental political right attached to the status of citizenship, that is, the right to decide in communion with other citizens about the membership of the polity. This right tells us why the decision of those European citizens in the UK that voted to leave the Union must be respected. What is less clear, however, is why, in a supra-national European polity premised upon the unity of the peoples of Europe (another way of saying the people of Europe), a decision of the UK government should bind those UK nationals who wish to retain their European citizenship. Viewed from this perspective, Mr. Tusk’s remarks are simply false: the future EU citizenship of UK nationals is not a domestic matter but an issue – perhaps the issue – for the Union as a whole to determine.

There are of course a wealth of objections to such a proposal. At a legal level, it would require a significant re-writing of the European Treaties and much EU secondary legislation. At the political level, it flies in the face of one of the central messages of the referendum, which rejected the free movement of persons while embracing the free movement of capital.

As concerns the first objection, re-opening the European treaties at this point in time bears significant risks yet also offers the opportunity for sustained political reflection about the future of the European enterprise. The de-coupling of European from national citizenship in the CJEU’s case-law has already begun to shift citizens’ entitlement to jointly decide about membership in the polity from the national to the European level. Extending that primordial political right to the case of the UK leaving the Union would certainly amount to a coup d’état, but it would not involve transforming the Union into a state – federal or otherwise.

In that context, and in response to the second political objection, let’s not forget that attempts to join neo-liberalism with parochial nationalism tend to yield pathological results. Surely, the disintegration of the political foundations of the Union cannot be parried with more free trade for unfree people. The crisis of political legitimacy of which the Brexit referendum is yet another symptom, should surely demand an EU project that is more, not less, centred on the needs and rights of its citizens. With Brexit, the waters around us have quite literally grown: as Bob Dylan once told us, the times they are a changin’. Now’s the time to make EU citizenship real.


SUGGESTED CITATION  Dawson, Mark; Augenstein, Daniel: After Brexit: Time for a further Decoupling of European and National Citizenship?, VerfBlog, 2016/7/14, https://verfassungsblog.de/brexit-decoupling-european-national-citizenship/, DOI: 10.17176/20160714-114950.

One Comment

  1. Ferdinand Weber Fri 15 Jul 2016 at 08:47 - Reply

    Your article touches the constitutional blueprint of the relationship between member states and the European Union, but also “the” precondition of a functioning democracy. Coming from these two points I would object your main thesis that says – supposing I understood it right – the EU is or should in some form be/get legally competent or at least politically accountable for a member state’s withdrawal decision considering status rights of (some) of the affected individuals (i.p. your para. 4).
    EU citizenship exists and unfolds normative purpose only in the framework of primary union law. The rights deriving from union citizenship are not only coupled to the different nationalities but also, as kind of an ahead lying “root agreement”, to the decision to stay in the Union. As soon as a state decides to withdraw, i.e. make use of the Art. 50 TFEU-procedure, which is equipped with the same normative substance and legitimacy as Art. 20, the rights deriving from the treaties cease to exist as soon as the withdrawal enters into force. Besides that: considering that there is no necessary consent of the people in codified union law (because they already act, as laid down in Art. 50 TFEU, through their member state’s organs?), in this case that consent was given in advance directly by them.
    Of course that was not your point, only the normative background. But the recall of primary union law’s normative structure clarifies the misunderstanding of the ECJ’s jurisprudence in Ruiz Zambrano: the – judicially given – fundamental status cannot reach out over the boundaries of primary law itself. The decision to leave may be tight, but is to be respected as a democratic decision of the people of the United Kingdom. Besides that: We all know that the ECJ’s concept of autonomy of the EU legal order and the assumption of a united people of Europe barely tells half the truth of the picture and is not qualified to outweigh a majority vote. That latter assumption, deriving from just one branch of public law theory, is rather fitting if one aims at splitting up decision making bodies in subdivisions, preparing to challenge that decision through strategic assemblies of the “outvoted” minority groups.
    That leads to the more problematic account of calling a self-standing union citizenship into being. Democracy’s own “fundamentum” is respecting the majority’s decision by the “outvoted” minority. Arguing with a “threat to a whole population” and propagating smoothing out the consequences of that decision by bringing forward supposedly individual EU-citizenship law rights that overcomes them, turns the structure and difference of this agreed and retrievable status upside down. Union citizenship is, and that’s the greatest difference to nationality status, easily retrievable: through primary law itself and a national decision activating the “leave”-procedure. The status hangs on primary law’s legal force and has neither special constitutional safeguard (as Art. 16 of the Grundgesetz provides) nor safeguards beyond the existence of its normative basis, the TFEU. In other words: Union citizenship has no constitutional protection mechanisms against majority decisions at EU level, maybe for good reasons. The decision is settled by the people of the affected member state. How fortunate will the attempt to factually ignore that with legal constructs look? And besides that: Was there or would there have been any substantial discussion about a individual opt-out of EU citizenship for people wanting to leave the EU if the whole voted for remain? I don’t think so, and for good reasons.
    One should wonder and remind him-/herself of the German discussion if the protected principles of Art. 79 III GG even bind “the people” (more modern: the political community) when giving itself a new constitution. It is totally undecided and maybe undecidable. That already is a complex and special discussion. Considering the EU, things are easier. There is no eternity clause at EU level, taking parts of EU law out of the democratic sphere. Even Maduro’s findings unfold meaning only if there still is a existent membership. It is a typical individualistic argument when one now points out to certain groups wanting to retain EU citizenship status even after “Brexit” while setting aside the decision of the whole (as is the recently often heard narrative, “the old” are to blame while it is known that the voting participation of “the young” was significantly behind the former).
    I think the card now drawn by many, bringing certain individual rights at the table (which are not at all safeguarded by primary law but open to democratically consented recantation), is a typical sign of the weakening of democracy. The real symptom of crisis for political legitimacy seems this way of arguing: extracting fragmented groups out of the voting body, circularly preformed for the argument’s goal itself and then put into place against the whole. It is surprising how fast the state, as the primary institution of democratic self-organization and -decision making turns into a leviathan in the eyes of some if they don’t see a personally acceptable decision. It is too easy using certain discontented groups selectively. That’s the point of democracy: it is build on acceptance of the majority vote, how irrational – in the eyes of some, not all – it might be. And because of that, arguing with a union law autonomy beyond that principle can’t be convincing.
    The options are clear and reasonable: gaining another member state’s citizenship (Germany’s nationality law explicitly allows maintaining the old one and concerning recent reports, that’s the way people go), or (for Northern Ireland and Scotland) deciding – again democratically – which association they prefer: UK or EU. Those decisions should then also be respected equally. Respecting the decision would also help more in (re)building trust in the EU legal order in other member states than a legal reach out for non-member state nationals.

Leave A Comment

WRITE A COMMENT

1. We welcome your comments but you do so as our guest. Please note that we will exercise our property rights to make sure that Verfassungsblog remains a safe and attractive place for everyone. Your comment will not appear immediately but will be moderated by us. Just as with posts, we make a choice. That means not all submitted comments will be published.

2. We expect comments to be matter-of-fact, on-topic and free of sarcasm, innuendo and ad personam arguments.

3. Racist, sexist and otherwise discriminatory comments will not be published.

4. Comments under pseudonym are allowed but a valid email address is obligatory. The use of more than one pseudonym is not allowed.




Explore posts related to this:
EU citizenship, Grzelczyk, Ruiz Zambrano, Scotland, brexit, rottmann


Other posts about this region:
Europa, Vereinigtes Königreich